Frasi di Morris Kline

Morris Kline è stato un matematico statunitense.

Fu docente di matematica e fecondo scrittore di storia della matematica, filosofia della matematica, e didattica della matematica; fu anche un efficace divulgatore di tematiche connesse con la matematica.

Kline trascorse la giovinezza a Brooklyn e Queens. Conseguito il diploma presso la "Boys High School" di Brooklyn, proseguì gli studi matematici presso la New York University, conseguendovi il titolo di B.Sc. nel 1930, il M.Sc. nel 1932, e il Ph.D. nel 1936.

Insegnò presso la New York University dal 1938 al 1975, con la sola interruzione dovuta al suo servizio presso lo U.S. Army Signals Corps nel periodo bellico; in tale periodo lavorò, come fisico, nei Laboratori di ricerca che perfezionarono il Radar.

Si dedicò soprattutto alla scrittura di numerosi articoli e di più di una dozzina di libri su vari aspetti della matematica, in particolare sull'insegnamento della medesima. In tale veste, fu uno dei protagonisti dell'acceso dibattito che si sviluppò negli Stati Uniti sulla "New Math" e la definizione dei curricola formativi in matematica, sia scolastici che universitari, negli anni '60 e '70.

Kline sottolineò con insistenza la necessità di insegnare le applicazioni e l'utilità della matematica, piuttosto che aspettarsi che un numero elevato di studenti ne apprezzasse il fascino intrinseco. Parallelamente, egli sollecitò affinché le ricerche matematiche si concentrassero sulla risoluzione di problemi applicativi posti in altri campi , piuttosto che costruire strutture concettuali autoreferenziali, capaci di suscitare quasi esclusivamente l'interesse di altri matematici puri.

Così riassunse alcune sue vedute nel 1986, nell'editoriale Focus, periodico della Mathematical Association of America:

In tutti i livelli di scuola, dalla primaria alla secondaria alla scuola superiore, la matematica viene insegnata come materia isolata, con pochi, se non del tutto assenti, legami con il mondo reale. Agli studenti la matematica appare quasi interamente connessa con questioni che non riguardano affatto l'essere umano.

✵ 1. Maggio 1908 – 10. Giugno 1992
Morris Kline: 42   frasi 0   Mi piace

Morris Kline: Frasi in inglese

“The Greeks failed to comprehend the infinitely large, the infinitely small, and infinite processes.”

Origine: Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times (1972), p. 57
Contesto: The Greeks failed to comprehend the infinitely large, the infinitely small, and infinite processes. They "shrank before the silence of the infinite spaces."

“The method has the form of the now-standard method of differential calculus, though it begs entirely the difficult theory of limits.”

Origine: Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times (1972), p. 346
Contesto: Fermat applied his method of tangents to many difficult problems. The method has the form of the now-standard method of differential calculus, though it begs entirely the difficult theory of limits.

“For these proofs Heron gave new proofs that avoided extending the lines, in order to meet the objection of anyone who would deny that the space was available for the extension.”

Origine: Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times (1972), p. 177
Contesto: Closely related to the problem of the parallel postulate is the problem of whether physical space is infinite. Euclid assumes in Postulate 2 that a straight-line segment can be extended as far as necessary; he uses this fact, but only to find a larger finite length—for example in Book I, Propositions 11, 16, and 20. For these proofs Heron gave new proofs that avoided extending the lines, in order to meet the objection of anyone who would deny that the space was available for the extension.

“The attempt to avoid a direct affirmation about infinite parallel straight lines caused Euclid to phrase the parallel axiom in a rather complicated way. He realized that, so worded, this axiom lacked the self-sufficiency of the other nine axioms, and there is good reason to believe that he avoided using it until he had to. Many Greeks tried to find substitute axioms for the parallel axiom or to prove it on the basis of the other nine. …Simplicius”

Origine: Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times (1972), p. 177
Contesto: The attempt to avoid a direct affirmation about infinite parallel straight lines caused Euclid to phrase the parallel axiom in a rather complicated way. He realized that, so worded, this axiom lacked the self-sufficiency of the other nine axioms, and there is good reason to believe that he avoided using it until he had to. Many Greeks tried to find substitute axioms for the parallel axiom or to prove it on the basis of the other nine.... Simplicius cites others who worked on the problem and says further that people "in ancient times" objected to the use of the parallel postulate.

“The relationship of point to line”

Origine: Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times (1972), p. 176
Contesto: The relationship of point to line bothered the Greeks and led Aristotle to separate the two. Though he admits points are on lines, he says that a line is not made up of points and that the continuous cannot be made up of the discrete. This distinction contributed also to the presumed need for separating number from geometry, since to the Greeks numbers were discrete and geometry dealt with continuous magnitudes.

“To avoid any assertion about the infinitude of the straight line, Euclid says a line segment”

Origine: Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times (1972), p. 175
Contesto: To avoid any assertion about the infinitude of the straight line, Euclid says a line segment (he uses the word "line" in this sense) can be extended as far as necessary. Unwillingness to involve the infinitely large is seen also in Euclid's statement of the parallel axiom. Instead of considering two lines that extend to infinity and giving a direct condition or assumption under which parallel lines might exist, his parallel axiom gives a condition under which two lines will meet at some finite point.

“Closely related to the problem of the parallel postulate is the problem of whether physical space is infinite. Euclid assumes”

Origine: Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times (1972), p. 177
Contesto: Closely related to the problem of the parallel postulate is the problem of whether physical space is infinite. Euclid assumes in Postulate 2 that a straight-line segment can be extended as far as necessary; he uses this fact, but only to find a larger finite length—for example in Book I, Propositions 11, 16, and 20. For these proofs Heron gave new proofs that avoided extending the lines, in order to meet the objection of anyone who would deny that the space was available for the extension.

“He had doubted the correctness of the law of refraction of light but when he found in 1661 that he could deduce it from his Principle, he not only resolved his doubts about the law but felt all the more certain that his Principle was correct.”

Origine: Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times (1972), p. 580
Contesto: Fermat knew that under reflection light takes the path requiring least time and, convinced that nature does indeed act simply and economically, affirmed in letters of 1657 and 1662 his Principle of Least Time, which states that light always takes the path requiring least time. He had doubted the correctness of the law of refraction of light but when he found in 1661 that he could deduce it from his Principle, he not only resolved his doubts about the law but felt all the more certain that his Principle was correct.... Huygens, who had at first objected to Fermat's Principle, showed that it does hold for the propagation of light in media with variable indices of refraction. Even Newton's first law of motion, which states that the straight line or shortest distance is the natural motion of a body, showed nature's desire to economize. These examples suggested that there might be a more general principle. The search for such a principle was undertaken by Maupertuis.

“The Pythagoreans associated good and evil with the limited and unlimited, respectively.”

Origine: Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times (1972), p. 175

Autori simili

John Nash photo
John Nash 8
matematico ed economista statunitense
Paul Dirac photo
Paul Dirac 3
fisico e matematico britannico
Niels Bohr photo
Niels Bohr 8
fisico e matematico danese
Christopher Morley photo
Christopher Morley 16
scrittore statunitense
Stephen Hawking photo
Stephen Hawking 38
matematico, fisico e cosmologo britannico
Louis-Victor Pierre Raymond de Broglie photo
Louis-Victor Pierre Raymond de Broglie 8
matematico e fisico francese
Bertrand Russell photo
Bertrand Russell 176
filosofo, logico e matematico gallese
Alfred Adler photo
Alfred Adler 7
matematico statunitense
Richard Feynman photo
Richard Feynman 35
fisico statunitense
Ludwig Wittgenstein photo
Ludwig Wittgenstein 112
filosofo e logico austriaco